Coda on Dual Service in Congress and as VP: Seth Barrett Tillman Replies
Note from Mike Dorf: In response to the doubts I raised about his argument concerning the constitutionality of Rep. Ryan (or anyone else) simultaneously serving in the House and as VP, Seth Barrett Tillman has written the following reply. In addition to addressing that concrete question, it nicely frames some important questions in constitutional interpretation. Now here's Seth.
----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
Professor
Dorf and I agree on (at least) one thing. The position – that the President and
Vice President are not Offices under the
United States (as that expression is used in the Incompatibility Clause) –
is not compelled by the text of the
Constitution. The text-reliant position is strengthened by various post-1789
documents and incidents, including, among others:
(i) President
Washington’s conduct in regard to accepting both the key to the Bastille from
LaFayette (1790) and the Louis XVI portrait from the French Ambassador (1791);
(ii) Secretary
Hamilton’s responsive correspondence to the United States Senate (1793);
(iii) Justice
Chase’s letter to Chief Justice Marshall (1802);
(iv) Justice
Story’s Commentaries (1833) and
McKnight’s treatise on election law (1878);
(v) The
absence of a continuous tradition of President’s issuing commissions to their successors
in office and to Vice Presidents (1789-present); and,
(vi) Justice
Miller’s opinion for the Supreme Court in United
States v. Mouat (1888); etc.
The post-1789
historical case improves the textual position. Admittedly, it does not quite
reach, what the British tabloids call, the stand-up-in-court-proof-of-adultery-in-the-royal-bedroom-through-photographic-evidence
standard.
Because
the pure text-reliant position is (arguably) insufficient, we turn to history.
Historical material buttresses the text-reliant position, but it still leaves Professor
Dorf (and many, many others) with fairly-held residual doubts. What then? The
interpreter at that point turns to other modalities or strategies of
interpretation. The modern approach is to turn to what is called constitutional
structure (at least where the text is less than what is reasonably clear).
Professor
Dorf writes: “there
is, in my view, enough wiggle room for the text to support what may turn out to
be an ahistorical view.” My problem with Michael’s position is
not that he is wrong; he is not wrong. But, that his statement lacks his
customary precision. His interpretive strategy – embracing structuralism absent
clear text – is open to (at least) several different interpretations
(independent of what he personally intended).
In other words, I am responding to his prior post’s original public meaning, not his (secretly held or otherwise ambiguous)
original intent.
(I) Structuralism As A Solution to Bona Fidé
Ambiguity. Here the interpreter
acknowledges that the key text – Office
under the United States in the Incompatibility Clause – is controlling. The
interpreter’s problem is that the text was ambiguous in 1789. Ambiguity here
may mean either: (A) it was subject to multiple fairly held understandings
in 1789; or (B) no one really thought about it in 1789, but if they had,
it would have been subject to multiple fairly held understandings. Structure
allows the interpreter to settle on one of those fairly held meanings by
importing into the Incompatibility Clause normative principles arising in
connection with related constitutional provisions. These other provisions are
helpful because they (unlike the Incompatibility Clause) speak with clarity.
Michael
cannot rely on this strategy in regard to the operative language here. Why? The
primary reason is that ambiguity is not something that one can merely assert.
It is an empirical claim which itself requires
some evidence. He has not put any
evidence forward that in 1789 the meaning of Office under the United States (as used in the Incompatibility
Clause) was in doubt.
There
is also some good reason to believe
that the Framers and the People thought about this issue and this language a
great deal and that a common specific meaning was widely held. Decisions taken
in regard to congressional incompatibility are taken by a single house acting
alone, absent presentment, absent bicameralism, and (in most cases) absent
meaningful or timely judicial review. Such legislative determinations do not require supermajorities, just simple
majorities: a majority of those voting, a quorum present. If the Framers had
chosen ambiguous language that would have let the majority oppress and exclude
the minority. In such circumstances, it stands to reason that the anti-federalists
would have objected. And I might add, rightly so. But where is there a record
of any such objection or anything like it?
The
second reason is more cheeky. Michael throws pure textualism overboard because
To be
sure, Tillman's textual argument is a good one. He uses a technique that
Akhil Amar has called “intra-textualism” to glean the meaning of a
term—“Office”--from how it and other terms are used in other parts of the
document. If we had only the text of the Constitution, I think I would be
persuaded by his reading. But the Constitution is not the perfect word of God.
What is
good for the (constitutional) goose is good for the (constitutional) gander. If
we cannot make use of intratextual meaning because the Constitution is not the
word of “God,” if we cannot discover the meaning of the Incompatibility
Clause’s Office under the United States
language by investigating how the same (or similar) text was used elsewhere in
the Constitution, then there is no reasonable warrant to look to the purposes
of other clauses either. If usage was not consistent and coherent across the
Constitution, then we lack any basis to assume strong aspirational or normative
consistency across provisions either. So this strategy will not do.
(II) Stucturalism In The Service Of Other Constitutional
Text. Here, Michael’s argument may be ... OK, the Incompatibility Clause does not forbid joint dual Member/VP
office-holding, but such dual office-holding undermines the purpose of other
constitutional provisions. Consider this hypothetical. A contested popular general
election is held and no one wins an Electoral College majority. Under Amendment
XII, the choice of the President falls to the House; the Vice President, the
Senate. What if the two bodies were to pick the same person. (Remember Lloyd Bentsen – in 1988, he received
electoral votes for both slots!) Could the same person hold both positions at
the same time? The Incompatibility Clause does not preclude it. No other
provision expressly forbids it. So you might say – well, yes, the same person
could hold both the presidency and vice presidency. But, you might also reasonably
argue that the entire or, at least, the primary purpose of the VP is to step
into the shoes of the President in the event of the latter’s death,
resignation, incapacity, conviction in impeachment proceedings, etc. So if the
same person holds both positions, then the whole (or nearly the whole) purpose of
the Constitution’s succession-related provisions has been frustrated and that
is sufficient warrant to forbid what the text does not otherwise expressly
forbid.
Michael
cannot rely on this strategy here. Consider the Constitution’s many clauses
relating to presentment and bicameralism. Was there widespread agreement in
1789 what these clause’s purposes were? Is there today? I do not think so. This
popular, academic, and judicial literature here is quite contentious. (Some
caused by me!) But even assuming this problem away, Ryan’s holding one seat in
the House and the presiding chair in the Senate hardly undermines the whole or, even, nearly the whole purpose
of these provisions. I think Michael has (at least elliptically) already
acknowledged that: “[I]f [dual office-holding were
permitted by a court] . . . I don’t think that would necessarily
be so bad.”
So this
strategy will not do either.
(III) Structuralism In The Service Of
Constitutional Aspirations Or (Founding-era or Modern) Norms. Unlike strategies
(I) and (II) above, this strategy is not driven by any express text. It relies
on unstated assumptions or aspirations connected to the Framers’ worldview, the
ideal of written constitutionalism, or our system’s federal design, etc. My own
view is that this strategy is inconsistent with the rule of law, but I am (unfortunately)
in the minority on this.
I will
further state that this strategy – more than any other strategy – more than
textualism – fairly applied – should lead the interpreter to permit dual
member-VP office-holding.
Why? For
the very sensible reasons explained by the Supreme Court of the United States
in Powell v. McCormack (1969). In Powell, the Court held that the House’s refusal to seat Congressman-elect
Powell, his exclusion based on a finding of corruption, was unconstitutional.
In other words, the House can only exclude a member based on qualifications expressly stated in the Constitution:
e.g., age, residency, and citizenship. Allegations of corruption, even if
proven, will not do. The Court’s holding was rooted in two deep structural
concerns. First, ours is a written constitution. A commitment to written
constitutionalism requires the Courts, Congress, and other political actors
(and, as an aspirational matter, maybe even legal academics speaking in the
name of the Constitution?) to respect the Constitution’s textual limits.
Congress is not free to subtract from extant express limitations, nor is it
free to fashion new ones beyond the express text.
More
importantly, restrictions on office-holding impinge on the freedom of the
People to choose their governors: a theme which runs continuously from 1776 to 1787,
and then to 1861-1865, and into the present of today and, hopefully, into our
tomorrows. The People’s freedom to choose their own governors should not be
limited by abstract policy-making concerns, common law decision-making, viz.
structuralism.
Structuralism
may have a role in other areas of
constitutional law, but not here, not in regard to dual office-holding. At
least, it ought not to; too much is put
at risk by it. I suppose that makes me a bit of a moralist. I have tried not to
be. And, as I said at the outset, I do not support text-free structuralism as a
legitimate modality of interpretation (even where, as here, it supports the
thrust of my position).
Professor
Dorf and I agree that a further discussion of Wisconsin law as it relates to
dual office-holding is too tangential for this blog. If you are still
interested in the Wisconsin law aspect . . . see Michael Stern’s
Point of Order blog (August 14,
2012), and CONLAWPROF (August 12 – August 17, 2012). This has been a fun party.
Two blog posts are “far too short a time to spend among you – [but] this is the END. I am going. I am leaving NOW. Good-Bye!”
Seth