Originalism on the Ground Part II
By Eric Segall
In my essay last week, “Originalism on the Ground,” I asked people who consider themselves “meaningful originalists” to respond to a series of questions. Michael Ramsey kindly posted on the Originalism Blog thoughtful answers to some of them. I can’t address all of Mike’s points here but would like to address a few of the major ones.
In my essay last week, “Originalism on the Ground,” I asked people who consider themselves “meaningful originalists” to respond to a series of questions. Michael Ramsey kindly posted on the Originalism Blog thoughtful answers to some of them. I can’t address all of Mike’s points here but would like to address a few of the major ones.
I wrote in my piece that most Supreme
Court cases and doctrine don't find much support in
originalism, to which Mike responded that “I don't see why this is a problem for
originalism. The originalist project, at
least for many people, isn't descriptive; it seeks to change the way the Court
and the legal culture think about judicial decision-making.”
That
is a fair response as long as people who believe that originalism is the preferred
method of constitutional interpretation advocate an approach that is different from the Court’s current non-originalist doctrine. Judge Bork would fall into that category
as would the younger Michael McConnell because they combined their originalism
with a strong presumption against the Court striking down the actions of other
political officials. Most of the New Originalists, however, reject that presumption (Mike might be an exception). When we are in Larry
Solum’s, Jack Balkin’s and Randy Barnett’s “construction zone,” we are dealing with a method of constitutional intepretation that in
large part replicates how the Court currently decides constitutional cases. Other self-styled originalists like Will Baude and Steve Sachs expressly claim that some form of originalism is already deeply embedded in the law despite the many changes in most litigated areas of constitutional law. These calls for the Court to use the label “originalism” to describe a method of
interpretation that is anything but that is a bit mystifying.
In
response to my argument that originalism simply can’t help us resolve most contemporary
contested constitutional questions (such as the validity of lethal injections
or whether the Constitution applies to Guantanamo Bay), Mike offers three
responses. First he agrees with me that if the relevant litigated “provisions
have hopelessly vague language and [hopelessly] contested histories,"
then, in his words, “judges lack authority to intervene against the political
branches.” I am glad Mike agrees with this but, as I said, most modern day “originalists”--and this group certainly includes Scalia, Thomas, Solum, Barnett and Balkin--do not.
Mike’s
second and third responses are similar. He argues that sometimes “constitutional
language and history is not hopelessly vague and contested (or at least it is
not … as to some controversies and applications)…. The fact that original meaning
doesn't supply an answer in all cases is not a reason to ignore it when it does
supply an answer.”
Similarly,
he disagrees with me about the extent to which originalism is unhelpful because
“the difficulties of reaching originalist answers are often overstated.” He
believes careful historical research and possibly employing interpretative
techniques consistent with original meaning can be helpful across a range of
constitutional questions."
These
objections are important and require much greater treatment than I can provide
here. For now, my responses are that first, expecting Supreme Court Justices or
their clerks to conduct careful historical analysis (as opposed to law office history)
is something of a fool’s errand. We have little data that this is possible and
much that it is not.
Second,
to the extent that Mike thinks that original meaning can provide helpful answers
to modern questions, he needs to address the difficult issue of applying
fixed original meaning to new facts. As Justice Scalia said in Minnesota v. Dickerson, the Founders
might not have accepted the “indignity” of being frisked by the police pursuant
to arrest (as allowed by Terry v. Ohio),
but because guns have become much smaller and more powerful since then, what is a “reasonable”
search may have changed. Similarly, in Citizens United, Justice Scalia said that even if the Founders
would have believed for-profit-corporations had no free speech rights beyond
those affirmatively granted by the state, the nature of corporations has changed so dramatically that a different result may be required today.
But, if what is “reasonable” changes or how we view corporations changes as
society does, why not “liberty,” “marriage,” and “sovereignty,” etc? But once
that move is allowed, then we have to inquire how original meaning, assuming it
is ascertainable, applies to changed facts and new circumstances. And, once
judges or scholars cross that great divide, originalism falls into itself, and originalism
and the living Constitution become indistinguishable.
The
moves made by Scalia in Dickerson and
Citizens United demonstrate an important
normative point about the entire originalist enterprise. It is simply never
enough to ascertain original meaning in the abstract. That is a job for
historians, not judges. In litigation, the original meaning must be derived in
some factual context. But, that context shifts inevitably over the years, which
is why we have disputed cases.
Applying law to shifting facts is always (absent a strong presumption of
constitutionality) a current enterprise. It is impossible to ask the people of
1787 what they would have meant had they known, for example, how
corporations or guns would change. So, at the end of the day, originalism is fundamentally unhelpful unless the facts have not changed (extremely
unlikely) or a strong presumption against finding political decisions
unconstitutional is embraced by judges. But, that presumption is missing from most contemporary originalist scholars. And, because
of the subjective nature of the entire enterprise of recreating past meaning,
without that presumption, originalism is living constitutionalism under another,
and much less transparent, label.